Obrázky na stránke
PDF
ePub

seems to have deviated from the common opinion about ideas.

We

an idea for its immediate object. In Ber-
keley's, the most important objects are
known without ideas.
In Locke's system,
there are two sources of our ideas, sensa-
tion and reflection. In Berkeley's, sensa-
tion is the only source, because of the objects
of reflection there can be no ideas.
know them without ideas. Locke divides
our ideas into those of substances, modes,
and relations. In Berkeley's system, there
are no ideas of substances, or of relations;
but notions only. And even in the class of
modes, the operations of our own minds
are things of which we have distinct notions;
but no ideas.

Though he sets out in his principles of knowledge, by telling us that it is evident the objects of human knowledge are ideas, and builds his whole system upon this principle; yet, in the progress of it, he finds that there are certain objects of human knowledge that are not ideas, but things which have a permanent existence. The objects of knowledge, of which we have no ideas, are our own minds, and their various operations, other finite minds, and the Supreme Mind. The reason why there can be no ideas of spirits and their operations, the author informs us is this, That We ought to do the justice to Malebranche ideas are passive, inert, unthinking beings; to acknowledge that, in this point, as well they cannot, therefore, be the image or as in many others, his system comes nearer likeness of things that have thought, and to Berkeley's than the latter seems willing will, and active power; we have notions of to own. That author tells us that there minds, and of their operations, but not are four different ways in which we come ideas. We know what we mean by think- to the knowledge of things. To know things ing, willing, and perceiving; we can rea- by their ideas, is only one of the four. [176] Bon about beings endowed with those He affirms that we have no idea of our powers, but we have no ideas of them. A own mind, or any of its modifications: that spirit or mind is the only substance or we know these things by consciousness, support wherein the unthinking beings or without ideas. Whether these two acute ideas can exist; but that this substance philosophers foresaw the consequences that which supports or perceives ideas, should may be drawn from the system of ideas, itself be an idea, or like an idea, is evidently taken in its full extent, and which were afterabsurd. wards drawn by Mr Hume, I cannot pretend to say. If they did, their regard to religion was too great to permit them to admit those consequences, or the principles with which they were necessarily connected.

He observes, farther, Princip. sect. 142, that "all relations, including an act of the mind, we cannot properly be said to have an idea, but rather a notion of the relations or habitudes between things. [175] But if, in the modern way, the word idea is extended to spirits, and relations, and acts, this is, after all, an affair of verbal concern; yet it conduces to clearness and propriety, that we distinguish things very different by different names.

[ocr errors]

However this may be, if there be so many things that may be apprehended and known without ideas, this very naturally suggests a scruple with regard to those that are left: for it may be said, If we can apprehend and reason about the world of spirits, without ideas, Is it not possible that we may apprehend and reason about a material world, without ideas? If consciousness and reflection furnish us with notions of spirits and of their attributes, without ideas, may not our senses furnish us with notions of bodies and their attributes, without ideas?

This is an important part of Berkeley's system, and deserves attention. We are led by it to divide the objects of human knowledge into two kinds. The first is ideas, which we have by our five senses; they have no existence when they are not perceived, and exist only in the minds of those Berkeley foresaw this objection to his who perceive them. The second kind of system, and puts it in the mouth of Hylas, objects comprehends spirits, their acts, and in the following words :-Dial. 3, Hylas. the relations and habitudes of things. Of" If you can conceive the mind of God, these we have notions, but no ideas. No idea can represent them, or have any similitude to them: yet we understand what they mean, and we can speak with understanding, and reason about them, without ideas.

This account of ideas is very different from that which Locke has given. In his system, we have no knowledge where we have no ideas. Every thought must have

Berkeley is one of the philosophers who really held the doctrine of ideas, erroneously, by Reid, at. tributed to all.-H.

without having an idea of it, why may not I be allowed to conceive the existence of matter, notwithstanding that I have no idea of it ?" The answer of Philonous is— "You neither perceive matter objectively, as you do an inactive being or idea, nor know it, as you do yourself, by a reflex act, neither do you immediately apprehend it by similitude of the one or the other, nor yet collect it by reasoning from that which you know immediately; all which makes the case of matter widely different from that of the Deity."

on the spirit, or thinking substance which perceives them, in that they are excited by the will of another and more powerful spirit; yet still they are ideas; and certainly no idea, whether faint or strong, can exist, otherwise than in a mind perceiving it." Principles, § 33.

Though Hylas declares himself satisfied | the mind. They are also less dependent with this answer, I confess I am not because, if I may trust the faculties that God has given me, I do perceive matter objectively that is, something which is extended and solid, which may be measured and weighed, is the immediate object of my touch and sight. [177] And this object I take to be matter, and not an idea. And, though I have been taught by philosophers, that what I immediately touch is an idea, and not matter; yet I have never been able to discover this by the most accurate attention to my own perceptions.

[ocr errors]

It were to be wished that this ingenious author had explained what he means by ideas, as distinguished from notions. The word notion, being a word in common language, is well understood. All men mean by it, the conception, the apprehension, or thought which we have of any object of thought. A notion, therefore, is an act of the mind conceiving or thinking of some object. The object of thought may be either something that is in the mind, or something that is not in the mind.

It may be something that has no existence, or something that did, or does, or shall exist. But the notion which I have of that object, is an act of my mind which really exists while I think of the object; but has no existence when I do not think of it. The word idea, in popular language, has precisely the same meaning as the word notion. But philosophers have another meaning to the word idea; and what that meaning is, I think, is very difficult to say. The whole of Bishop Berkeley's system depends upon the distinction between notions and ideas; and, therefore, it is worth while to find, if we are able, what those things are which he calls ideas, as distinguished from notions.

66

are

For this purpose, we may observe, that he takes notice of two kinds of ideas-the ideas of sense, and the ideas of imagination. "The ideas imprinted on the senses by the Author of Nature," he says, called real things; and those excited in the imagination, being less regular, vivid, and constant, are more properly termed ideas, or images of things, which they copy and represent. [178] But then our sensations, be they never so vivid and distinct, are nevertheless ideas; that is, they exist in the mind, or are perceived by it as truly as the ideas of its own framing. The ideas of sense are allowed to have more reality in them-that is, to be more strong, orderly, and coherent-than the creatures of

Does Reid mean to surrender his doctrine, that perception is a conception-that extension and figure are not known by sense, but are notions suggested on the occasion of sensation? If he does not, his lan. guage in the text is inaccurate,-H.

From this passage we see that, by the ideas of sense, the author means sensations; and this, indeed, is evident from many other passages, of which I shall mention a few.-Principles, § 5. "Light and colours, heat and cold, extension and figurein a word, the things we see and feel-what are they but so many sensations, notions, ideas, or impressions on the sense?-and is it possible to separate, even in thought, any of these from perception? For my part, I might as easily divide a thing from itself." § 18. "As for our senses, by them we have the knowledge only of our sensations, ideas, or those things that are immediately perceived by sense, call them what you will;-but they do not inform us that things exist without the mind, or unperceived, like to those which are perceived." § 25. "All our ideas, sensations, or the things which we perceive, by whatever names they may be distinguished, are visibly inactive; there is nothing of power or agency included in them."

This, therefore, appears certain—that, by the ideas of sense, the author meant the sensations we have by means of our senses. I have endeavoured to explain the meaning of the word sensation, Essay I., chap. 1, [p. 229,] and refer to the explication there given of it, which appears to me to be perfectly agreeable to the sense in which Bishop Berkeley uses it.*

As there can be no notion or thought but in a thinking being; so there can be no sensation but in a sentient being. [179] It is the act or feeling of a sentient being; its very essence consists in its being felt. Nothing can resemble a sensation, but a similar sensation in the same or in some other mind. To think that any quality in a thing that is inanimate can resemble a sensation, is a great absurdity. In all this, I cannot but agree perfectly with Bishop Berkeley; and I think his notions of sensa

How it can be.asserted that by ideas of sense

Berkeley meant only what Reid did by sensations, I cannot comprehend. That the former used ideas of sense and sensations as convertible expressions, is true. But then Berkeley's sensation was equivalent to Reid's sensation plus his perception. This is mani fest even by the passages adduced in the text. In that from § v. of the "Principles," Berkeley ex. pressly calls extension and figure sensations. But it is a fundamental principle of Reid's philosophy, not only that neither extension nor figure, but that none of the primary qualities, are sensations. make a single quotation-"The primary qualities," he says, "are, cither sensations, nor are they the resemblances of sensations."-Infra, p. 238.-H.

Το

tion much more distinct and accurate than Locke's, who thought that the primary qualities of body are resemblances of our sensations, but that the secondary are not. That we have many sensations by means of our external senses, there can be no doubt; and, if he is pleased to call those ideas, there ought to be no dispute about the meaning of a word. But, says Bishop Berkeley, by our senses, we have the knowledge only of our sensations or ideas, call them which you will. I allow him to call them which he will; but I would have the word only in this sentence to be well weighed, because a great deal depends upon it.

For, if it be true that, by our senses, we have the knowledge of our sensations only, then his system must be admitted, and the existence of a material world must be given. up as a dream. No demonstration can be more invincible than this. If we have any knowledge of a material world, it must be by the senses: but, by the senses, we have no knowledge but of our sensations only; and our sensations have no resemblance of anything that can be in a material world.† The only proposition in this demonstration which admits of doubt is, that, by our senses, we have the knowledge of our sensations only, and of nothing else. If there are objects of the senses which are not sensations, his arguments do not touch them: they may be things which do not exist in the mind, as all sensations do; they may be things of which, by our senses, we have notions, though no ideas; just as, by consciousness and reflection, we have notions of spirits and of their operations, without ideas or sensations. [180]

Shall we say, then, that, by our senses, we have the knowledge of our sensations only; and that they give us no notion of anything but of our sensations? Perhaps this has been the doctrine of philosophers, and not of Bishop Berkeley alone, otherwise he would have supported it by arguments. Mr Locke calls all the notions we have by our senses, ideas of sensation; and in this has been very generally followed. Hence it seems a very natural inference, that ideas

Here again we have a criticism which proceeds on the erroneous implication, that Locke meant by sensation what teid himself did. If for sensation we substitute perception, (and by sensation Locke denoted both sensation proper and perception proper,) there remains nothing to censure; for Reid main tains that " our senses give us a direct and a distinct notion of the primary qualities, and inform us what they are in themselves "(infra, p. 237 ;) which is only Locke's meaning in other words. The same observation applies to many of the following passages.-H. See the last note.-H.

But, unless that be admitted, which the natural conviction of mankind certifics, that we have an immediate perception-a consciousness-of external and extended existences, it makes no difference, in regard to the conclusion of the Idealist, whether what we are conscious of in perception be supposed an entity in the mind, (an idea in Reid s meaning,) or a modification of the mind, (a notion or conception.) See above, p. 128, notes *.-H.

of sensation are sensations. But philosophers may err: let us hear the dictates of common sense upon this point.

Suppose I am pricked with a pin, I ask, Is the pain I feel, a sensation? Undoubtedly it is. There can be nothing that resembles pain in any inanimate being. But I ask again, Is the pin a sensation? To this question I find myself under a necessity of answering, that the pin is not a sensation, nor can have the least resemblance to any sensation. The pin has length and thickness, and figure and weight. A sensation can have none of those qualities. I am not more certain that the pain I feel is a sensation, than that the pin is not a sensation; yet the pin is an object of sense; and I am as certain that I perceive its figure and hardness by my senses, as that I feel pain when pricked by it.'

Having said so much of the ideas of sense in Berkeley's system, we are next to consider the account he gives of the ideas of imagination. Of these he says, Principles, § 28-" I find I can excite ideas in my mind at pleasure, and vary and shift the scene as oft as I think fit. It is no more than willing; and straightway this or that idea arises in my fancy; and by the same power it is obliterated, and makes way for another. This making and unmaking of ideas, doth very properly denominate the mind active. Thus much is certain, and grounded on experience. Our sensations," he says, “are called real things; the ideas of imagination are more properly termed ideas, or images of things" that is, as I apprehend, they are the images of our sensations. [181] It might surely be expected that we should be well acquainted with the ideas of imagination, as they are of our making; yet, after all the Bishop has said about them, I am at a loss to know what they are.

I would observe, in the first place, with regard to these ideas of imagination-that they are not sensations; for surely sensation is the work of the senses, and not of imagination; and, though pain be a sensation, the thought of pain, when I am not pained, is no sensation.

I observe, in the second place-that I can find no distinction between ideas of imagination and notions, which the author says are not ideas. I can easily distinguish be

This illustration is taken from Des Cartes. In this paragraph, the term sensation is again not used in the extension given to it by the philosophers in question.-H.

+ Berkeley's real words are- The ideas imprinted on the Senses by the Author of Nature are called real things, and those excited in the Imagination being less regular, vivid and constant, are more properly termed ideas or images of things, which they copy and represent. But then our Sensations, be they never so vivid and, distinct, are nevertheless ideasthat is, they exist in the mind, or are perceived by it, as truly as the ideas of its own franiing." Sect. xxxiii.-H.

tween a notion and a sensation. It is one thing to say, I have the sensation of pain. It is another thing to say, I have a notion of pain. The last expression signifies no more than that I understand what is meant by the word pain. The first signifies that I really feel pain. But I can find no distinction between the notion of pain and the imagination of it, or indeed between the notion of anything else, and the imagination of it. I can, therefore, give no account of the distinction which Berkeley makes between ideas of imagination and notions, which, he says, are not ideas. They seem to me perfectly to coincide.*

He seems, indeed, to say, that the ideas of imagination differ not in kind from those of the senses, but only in the degree of their regularity, vivacity, and constancy. They are," says he, "less regular, vivid, and constant." This doctrine was afterwards greedily embraced by Mr Hume, and makes a main pillar of his system; but it cannot be reconciled to common sense, to which Bishop Berkeley professes a great regard. For, according to this doctrine, if we compare the state of a man racked with the gout, with his state when, being at perfect ease, he relates what he has suffered, the difference of these two states is only this-that, in the last, the pain is less regular, vivid, and constant, than in the first. [182] We cannot possibly assent to this. Every man knows that he can relate the pain he suffered, not only without pain, but with pleasure; and that to suffer pain, and to think of it, are things which totally differ in kind, and not in degree only.+

We see, therefore, upon the whole, that, according to this system, of the most important objects of knowledge—that is, of

Yet the distinction of ideas, strictly so called, and notions, is one of the most common and important in the philosophy of mind. Nor do we owe it, as has been asserted, to Berkeley. It was virtually taken by Des Cartes and the Cartesians, in their discrimination of

ideas of imagination and ide s.of intelligence; it was in terms vindicated against Locke, by Serjeant, Stil. lingfleet, Norris, Z. Mayne, Bishop Brown, and others; Bonnet signalized it; and, under the contrast of Anschauungen -and Begriffe, it has long been an established and classical discrimination with the philosophers of Germany. Nay, Reid himself suggests it in the distinction he requires between ima. gination and conception, a distinction which he unfor

tunately did not carry out, and which Mr Stewart stilh more unhappily again perverted. See below, p. 371. The terms notion and conception, (or more correctly concept in this sense,) should be reserved to express what we comprehend but cannot picture in imagination, such as, à relation, a general term, &c. The word idea, as one prostituted to all mean. ings, it were perhaps better altogether to discard. As for the representations of imagination or phantasy, I would employ the terms image or phantasm, it being distinctly understood that these terms are ap plied to denote the re-presentations, not of our visible perceptions merely, as the terms taken literally would indicate, but of our sensible perceptions in general.

H.

There is here a confusion between pain considered as a feeling, and as the cognition of a feeling, to which the philosophers would object.-H.

He

spirits, of their operations, and of the relations of things-we have no ideas at all;" we have notions of them, but not ideas; the ideas we have are those of sense, and those of imagination. The first are the sensations we have by means of our senses, whose existence no man can deny, because he is conscious of them; and whose nature hath been explained by this author with great accuracy. As to the ideas of imagination, he hath left us much in the dark. He makes them images of our sensations; though, according to his own doctrine, nothing can resemble a sensation but a sensation.† seems to think that they differ from sensations only in the degree of their regularity, vivacity, and constancy. But this cannot be reconciled to the experience of mankind; and, besides this mark, which cannot be admitted, he hath given us no other mark by which they may be distinguished from notions. Nay, it may be observed, that the very reason he gives why we can have no ideas of the acts of the mind about its ideas, nor of the relations of things, is applicable to what he calls ideas of imagination. Principles, § 142. "We may not, I think, strictly be said to have an idea of an active being, or of an action, although we may be said to have a notion of them. I have some knowledge or notion of my mind, and its acts about ideas, in as much as I know or understand what is meant by these words. [I will not say that the terms Idea and Notion may not be used convertibly, if the world will have it so. But yet it conduces to clearness and propriety that we distinguish things very different by different names.] It is also to be remarked, that all relations including an act of the mind, we cannot so properly be said to have an idea, but rather a notion of the relations and habitudes between things." From this it follows, that our imaginations are not properly ideas, but notions, because they include an act of the mind. [183] For he tells us, in a passage already quoted, that they are creatures of the mind, of its own framing, and that it makes and unmakes them as it thinks fit, and from this is properly denominated active. If it be a good reason why we have not ideas, but notions only of relations, because they include an act of the mind, the same reason must lead us to conclude, that our imagina tions are notions and not ideas, since they are made and unmade by the mind as it thinks fit: and, from this, it is properly denominated active.+

[ocr errors]

That is, no images of them in the phantasy Reid himself would not say that such could be imagined.--H.

† Berkeley does not say so in the meaning sup. posed.-H.

t Imagination 18 an ambiguous word; it means either the act of imagining, or the product-ie, the image imagined. Of the former, Berkeley held, we can form a notion, but not an idea, in the sense he

When so much has been written, and so many disputes raised about ideas, it were desirable that we knew what they are, and to what category or class of beings they belong. In this we might expect satisfaction in the writings of Bishop Berkeley, if anywhere, considering his known accuracy and precision in the use of words; and it is for this reason that I have taken so much pains to find out what he took them to be.

After all, if I understand what he calls the ideas of sense, they are the sensations which we have by means of our five senses; but , they are, he says, less properly termed ideas. I understand, likewise, what he calls notions; but they, says he, are very different from ideas, though, in the modern way, often called by that name.

The ideas of imagination remain, which are most properly termed ideas, as he says; and, with regard to these, I am still very much in the dark. When I imagine a lion or an elephant, the lion or elephant is the object imagined. The act of the mind, in conceiving that object, is the notion, the conception, or imagination of the object. If besides the object, and the act of the mind about it, there be something called the idea of the object, I know not what it is.*

|

representatives of external objects of sense; yet they have neither colour, nor smell, nor figure, nor motion, nor any sensible quality. I revere the authority of philosophers, especially where they are so unanimous; but until I can comprehend what they mean by ideas, I must think and speak with the vulgar.

In sensation, properly so called, I can distinguish two things-the mind, or sentient being, and the sensation. Whether the last is to be called a feeling or an operation, I dispute not; but it has no object distinct from the sensation itself. If in sensation there be a third thing, called an idea, I know not what it is.

In perception, in remembrance, and in conception, or imagination, I distinguish three things-the mind that operates, the operation of the mind, and the object of that operation. [185] That the object perceived is one thing, and the perception of that object another, I am as certain as I can be of anything. The same may be said of conception, of remembrance, of love and hatred, of desire and aversion. In all these, the act of the mind about its object is one thing, the object is another thing. There must be an object, real or imaginary, distinct from the operation of the mind about it. Now, if in these operations the

three I have mentioned, I know not what it is, nor have been able to learn from all that has been written about ideas. And if the doctrine of philosophers about ideas confounds any two of these things which I have mentioned as distinct-if, for example, it confounds the object perceived with the perception of that object, and represents them as one and the same thing-such doctrine is altogether repugnant to all that I am able to discover of the operations of my own mind; and it is repugnant to the common sense of mankind, expressed in the structure of all languages.

If we consult other authors who have treated of ideas, we shall find as little satis-idea be a fourth thing different from the faction with regard to the meaning of this philosophical term. [184] The vulgar have adopted it; but they only mean by it the notion or conception we have of any object, especially our more abstract or general notions. When it is thus put to signify the operation of the mind about objects, whether in conceiving, remembering, or perceiving, it is well understood. But phi losophers will have ideas to be the objects of the mind's operations, and not the operations themselves. There is, indeed, great variety of objects of thought. We can think of minds, and of their operations; of bodies, and of their qualities and relations. If ideas are not comprehended under any of these classes, I am at a loss to comprehend what they are.

In ancient philosophy, ideas were said to be immaterial forms, which, according to one system, existed from all eternity; and, according to another, are sent forth from the objects whose form they are. + In modern philosophy, they are things in the mind, which are the immediate objects of all our thoughts, and which have no existence when we do not think of them. They are called the images, the resemblances, the

uses the term; whereas, of the latter, we can form
an idea by merely repeating the imaginatory act.-
Reid's misconception on this point, see Note

by the name of idea was sent off from
ancient philosophy.-11,

CHAPTER XII.

OF THE SENTIMENTS OF MR HUME.

Two volumes of the "Treatise of Human Nature" were published in 1739, and the third in 1740. The doctrine contained in this Treatise was published anew in a more popular form in Mr Hume's "Philosophical Essays," of which there have been various editions. What other authors, from the

See Note B.-H.

+ If there be an imaginary object distinct from the act of imagination, where does it exist? It cannot be external to the mind-for, ex hypothesi, it is ima ginary; and, if in the mind i self, distinct from the act of imagination-why, what is this but the very crudest doctrine of species For Reid's puzzle, see Note B. -II.

« PredošláPokračovať »